Robert Nozick?s interpretation of libertarianism, as a form of society guided by the invisible hand outwith the influence of the state, has generated criticism from many areas of the political spectrum. In order to avoid getting embedded in abstraction, attempts to directly address the structure of his interpretation of libertarianism must focus on testing the internal degree of theoretical cohesion, in regards to his perception of what values constitute the term libertarianism, and the external compatibility of this definition within his minarchic-capitalist outlook. Such a task will hereby be undertaken in a two-part investigation into Nozick?s philosophical thought; firstly that of critically examining the extent of rapport between selfownership and inviolable liberty, in regards to libertarianism, and secondly the condition of these in regards to free-exchange capitalism. To facilitate this exercise, Nozick?s libertarian thought will be summarised and referred to into three key aspects: a) the jurisdiction of self- ownership is the sanctuary of liberty, and that there are ?things no person or group may do to them[1]? without resulting in their violation b) the state is not a moral agent, and that only the ?minimal state, limited to the narrow functions of protection against force, theft, fraud, enforcement of contracts, and so on, is justified[2]? and not in violation of personal liberty c) property ownership is an extension of self-ownership, and that only voluntary exchange ? i.e. without the interference of government ? can preserve liberty In regards to etymology, the use of the term libertarianism is disputed.Historically, libertarianism has been associated with left-anarchism as described by Joseph Dejacque, expressed to be the ?abolition of government in all its guises...abolition of personal property, ownership of the soil...and of anything that is an instrument of labour, production or consumption[3]?. What he proposed to replace capitalism and the state was ?collective property, one and indivisible, held in common[4]?. The emergence of right-libertarian etymology as a self-identifying school of thought, on the other hand, has been reflected upon by right-libertarian Murray Rothbard in his statement that the term was ?captured...from the enemy[5]?. The distinction between the two has been articulated in the reflection that ?libertarianism...had long been simply a polite word for left- wing anarchists...for anti-private property anarchists, either of the communist or syndicalist variety. But now we had taken in over... since we were proponents of individual liberty and therefore of the individual?s right to his property[6]?.Libertarianism is therefore a contested term in regards to property in particular[7], so for the purposes of this essay libertarianism will allude to Nozick?s right- libertarian interpretation, unless otherwise specified. The premise for Nozick?s interpretation of libertarianism lies in a two-part claim that human rights are inviolable and that human beings are ends in themselves and thusly self- owners (a). What is implied by his argument is given that human beings are self-owners and have inviolable rights, it only follows that they ought to have complete jurisdiction over their own activity, save cases where it infringes upon the liberty of others, and that any violations of this private sphere are a violation of liberty de facto[8].Self-ownership and inviolable rights to liberty are thusly considered equitable by Nozick and advocates of his school of thought, wherein the right to liberty transpires from a right to self-ownership[9]. This, if respected, ought to guarantee the sanctity of liberty. It is this first point that ought to be held to scrutiny first of all. So as to test the compatibility between inviolable rights and self-ownership, it is helpful and constructive to specify that the latter value in a libertarian context must be comprehensive ? in other words, that ?there is no part of the self and its capacities that are unownable[10]?.To suggest otherwise would imply that there were parts of ourselves that could be intruded upon or owned that would not as a result violate our liberty and self-ownership, a notion which would be incompatible with this particular form of libertarianism. Dr Colin Bird, Associate Professor of Politics and Director of the Program in Political Philosophy, Policy and Law in the University of Virginia, remarked on an interesting discrepancy between self-ownership and inviolable rights which deserves deliberation in regards to the minarchical state as a public agent. Nozick?s claim that liberty disrupts patterned and end-state theories, leading to their resulting need to continuously violate liberty to maintain themselves, comes under considerable scrutiny in regards to the public agent as a protector of self- ownership and inviolable rights. Bird, to raise this issue, asks ?in the absence of any further normative considerations, does the inviolability of self-ownership rights automatically follow? Just how far does the fact of universal comprehensive self-ownership automatically constrain a public agent?s view of what it might mean to act legitimately on behalf of a community of...self- owners?[11]?. The answer to the first question of compatibility, shared as a common destination with the first part of this text, is largely answerable by the conclusions of the second. It can be said of the public agent, the minimal state, that it ought to be aware that individual self- owners are comprehensive and their rights are inviolable. This point already raises a problem for the public agent, for according to Nozick?s theory that it must exist to protect the sanctity of these two core libertarian values, it is at some point brought to a compromise that libertarians of the propertarian tradition could find to be significantly alarming. What if, for example, the public agent knows that a minor violation ? say the confiscation of a gun ? would prevent a more significant violation, a mass murder perhaps? As murder counts as a violation of liberty and property, following injury or death, the public agent is forced to violate one liberty in the name of another, implying that violations by the public agent are more legitimate then violations by non-pubic agents. This begs the question of whether or not it would then be illegitimate for the public agent to recognize a ?trade-off of a relatively harmless violation for the prevention of a very harmful one[12]?. At this point, we have reached a stage where violation and the distribution of violation is decided by a central authority in a universal manner so as to protect a community of self- owners in a utilitarian manner, as the avocation of non-violation seems not to be equitable to its prevention in itself. A pattern of systematic and utilitarian suppression thusly re-emerges, in such a manner that the public agent decides that it should, directly or indirectly, ?coerce citizens into respecting the self- ownership rights of others[13]?. The libertarian interpretation of Nozick is therefore forced either to negate the minimal state, self-ownership or inviolable liberty in order to avoid this paradox, for under the current paradigm some violations are passively necessitated once all outwith its theoretically limited jurisdiction are regarded as a ?community of self-owners[14]? ? a reality and compromise readily admitted to by libertarian theorist Lomasky[15]?. Following the first signs of internal contradiction in statement (a) in regards to self- ownership being compatible with inviolable rights, the next logical step is to consider whether Nozick?s argument that ?the state...[is] justified...only in so far as it protects people against force[16]? (b) can resolve this problem. In regards to the internal coherence of the statement that minarchy can preserve the conditions of (a), this position has been called up upon from within the self-prescribed anti- authoritarian right in the form of anarcho-capitalist Gerard Cassey?s accusation that, ?states are criminal organizations...not just the obviously totalitarian or repressive ones[17]?, describing the very existence of a state as ?a monopoly of allegedly legitimate force over the inhabitants of a determinate territory financed by a compulsory levy imposed on those inhabitants[18]?. On this line of thought, he accuses Nozick of being a minarchist and not a libertarian on the grounds that he is willing to accept a non- voluntary state that enforces non- violence, and that self-ownership is incompatible with even the most limited form of minarchy. This perspective reflects on the state?s potential to coerce as being an ispo facto violation of liberty, and holds Nozick?s second statement that the only legitimate state in regards to libertarianism is a minimal one to account. The link between Nozick?s support of a minimal state and the contradiction to be found within his support of it as a libertarian ? again, testing each of his statements in isolation for coherence ? can be revealed from an existential reflection on authoritarianism and coercion. If we are to cogitate on the origin of libertarianism as a negation of oppression, exploitation and coercion, then it must follow that the presence of a body capable of exercising these features be called to scrutiny. As demonstrated in the deliberations above upon the public agent as a violator, it becomes apparent that this source of authority is already taking a moral stance[19] ? albeit of its own interpretation ? as to how to best protect the community of self-owners through a series of continuous trade-offs between violations of various scales and their prevention or punishment. Following the exercise of validity and negation, proposal (b) can be tested for external cohesion in regards to the consequential negative externality its existence has on (a) by considering the counter-proposal that ?what will happen to the threatened individual, should he not comply...[is also that] which renders him unfree when the threat is made?, provided the implementation of the threat[20]. This line of thought was extensively articulated by professor emeritus Michael Taylor, who defined coercion by the inclusion of the threat of it. In this case, political power, and thus oppression and coercion, are defined by the ability to make the deviation from an individual?s primary choice of action to a secondary one a rational choice in the face of punishment[21]. The argument that such a presence protects liberty as Nozick and advocates of his school of thought envision it has already been repealed by the incompatibility between self- ownership and inviolable liberty, as the state ends up in its own end-state form, permanently enforcing the protection of liberty. Yet the contradiction of a minarchy with libertarian values extends in regards to the notion of self-ownership, as the threat of punishment in itself provides an external limitation to the private sphere of liberty, where a moral abstention from violating others? liberty does not suffice in this respect. The possession of the ability to, directly through enforcement or indirectly through the ability to enforce, affect individual?s actions in such a manner becomes the embodiment of the oppression libertarians theoretically struggle to abolish[22].Taylor points to the fact that any ?rational individual would prefer not to be the recipient of a threat, and after a threat had been made, he would prefer to be back in the pre-threat situation[23]?, and that it follows that only the absence of coercion? active or potential ? can articulate a libertarian society. In this case, the existence of a public agent or minimal state de facto infringes upon the jurisdiction of self-ownership, as part of one?s actions or disposition towards them is restricted through the monopolised right to punish them by the public agent[24]. The surrendering of self- ownership in the name of self- ownership thus, according to this line of argument, becomes an inevitable result of Nozick?s second clause. We are therefore left with the consequences of statement (b) having an externally contradictory effect to the validity of (a), negating the possibility of inviolable rights and self-ownership. If Nozick?s first statement is threatened by an internal contradiction between self- ownership and inviolable rights, and his second statement negates the validity of the first regardless of whether the former argument can stand in isolation, deductive logic points to Nozick?s third clause (c) ? that if humans are self-owners, they are also owners of their income, property and labour ? as a final point of scrutiny in regards to this particular validity-exercise. In regards to this statement, Nozick argues that statement (a) is validated and protected through his interpretation of justice, materialized by the entitlement theory. If it is to be the case that justice in acquisition be defined by non-violation[25]?, this claim appears to be refuted by his own rejection of the unjust accumulation of property and wealth through inheritance, that leads to ?continuing inequalities of wealth and position...[making] the resulting inequalities seem unfair[26]?. This would be an internal contradiction in statement (c), resolvable only by the possible interference of the state[27]. In regards to justice in transfer, Nozick?s additional belief that ?seizing the results of someone?s labour is equivalent to seizing hours from him...making them a part-time owner of you[28]? would seem to excerpt an external contradiction on clause (a), as surplus value would assume the same violation as imposed tax in regards to the labour-capital relationship, given that the tax-related months per year of unpaid labour would be equated to the unfavourable ratio of labour hours and wage value. In this sense, alienationwould completely negate the Nozickian claim that self-ownership encompassed ownership of one?s own labour, product, and property[29]. The externalities of the principle of rectification of justice upon claims (a) and (b), finally, would be those of the re- emerging end-state and violator of liberty mentioned previously. Having tested and examined each of Nozick?s three statements in separation and in relation to one another, the following observations can be made. In regards to his first clause, the implied equitability of inviolable rights and self- ownership is subject to internal contradiction, insofar that if self-ownership were to be considered and inviolable right, it would have to be enforced, thus giving rise to a contradiction in the context of libertarianism and its propertarian tradition. In regards to the second statement on the existence of a minimal state, this clause causes the active demise of statement (a) given the state, regardless of how minimal in form, becomes existential violation of ownership and liberty, given the arising need of a moral trade-off of utilitarian violations. It exceeds the so-called jurisdiction of its minimalistic purpose, becoming yet another end-state of systematic violation in the name of the self-owned community. Finally, in reference to the third claim that self-ownership is to encompass ownership of labour, property, and product, the justice in acquisition fails to persevere when faced with inheritable tradition, surplus- value exploitation and alienation, and a regression towards the state to yet again act as a moderating, distributive benefactor of justice and wealth, creating both an internal contradiction in values as well as a violation of all that is represented by the terms self-ownership and inviolable rights. [1] Nozick, Robert, ?Anarchy, State and Utopia?, Basic Books 1974, p. ix [2] Ibid [3] Graham, Robert, ? Anarchism. A Documentary History of Libertarian Ideas. Volume One: From Anarchy to Anarchism (300CE to 1939)?, Black Rose Books 2006, p. 60 [4] Ibid, pg. 61 [5] Murray N., Rothbard, ?The Betrayal of the American Right?, Ludwig von Mises Institute, 2007, p. 83 [6] Ibid [7] Avineri, Shlomo; de-Shalit, Avner, ?Communitarianism and Individualism?, Oxford University Press 1992, p. 137 [8] Rothbard, M. ?Power and Market?, Institute of Human Studies 1970, p. 76 [9] Wolff, Jonathan, ?Robert Nozick. Property, Justice and the Minimal State?, Polity Press 1991, p.4 [10] Bird, Collin. ?The Myth of Liberal Individualism?, Cambridge University Press, 1999, p. 143 [11] Ibid, pg. 148 [12] Ibid, p. 151 [13] Ibid, p. 149 [14] Ibid, p. 152 [15] Lomasky, L, ?Persons, Rights and the Moral Community?, Oxford University Press, 1987, p. 151 [16] Wolff, Jonathan, ?Robert Nozick. Property, Justice and the Minimal State?, Polity Press 1991, p. 30 [17] Casey, Gerard, (2013) ?Libertarian Anarchy: Against the State?, Notre Dame Philosophical Reviews. An Electronic Journal?, available at (http://ndpr.nd.edu/news/40697-libertarian-anarchy-against-the-state/), [accessed: 03/10/13] [18] Ibid [19] a prospect which is antagonistic to right and individualist libertarians as found in Nozick?s statement (b) [20] Taylor, Michael, ?Community, Anarchy and Liberty?, Cambridge University Press 1985, p. 144 [21] Ibid, p. 11 [22] Ibid, p.11 [23] Ibid, p. 146 [24] Norman, Richard, ?Free and Equal. A Philosophical Examination of Political Values?, Oxford University Press 1987, p. 36 [25] Barry, Norman P., ?On Classical Liberalism and Libertarianism?, Macmillan Press 1989, p. 151 [26] Nozick, Robert, ?The Examined Life. Philosophical Meditations?, Simon and Schuster, 1989, p. 30 [27] Ibid [28] Nozick, Robert, ?Anarchy, State and Utopia?, Basic Books, 1974, p. 172 [29] Meszaros, Istvan, ?Marx?s Theory of Alienation?, Merlin Press 1970, p. 154 Bibliography Books: Avineri, Shlomo; de-Shalit, Avner, ?Communitarianism and Individualism?, Oxford University Press, 1992 Bird, Collin. ?The Myth of Liberal Individualism?, Cambridge University Press, 1999 Cohen, G. A, ?Self-Ownership, Freedom and Equality?, Cambridge University Press, 1995 Godwin, William, ?Enquiry Concerning Political Justice?, Penguin Books, 1985 Graham, Robert, ? Anarchism. A Documentary History of Libertarian Ideas. Volume One: From Anarchy to Anarchism (300CE to 1939)?, Black Rose Books, 2006 Lomasky, ?Persons, Rights and the Moral Community?, Oxford University Press, 1987 Meszaros, Istvan, ?Marx?s Theory of Alienation?, Merlin Press, 1970 Norman, Richard, ?Free and Equal. A Philosophical Examination of Political Values?, Oxford University Press, 1987 Nozick, Robert, ?Anarchy, State and Utopia?, Basic Books, 1974 Nozick, Robert, ?The Examined Life. Philosophical Meditations?, Simon and Schuster, 1989 Rothbard, M., ?Power and Market?, Institute of Human Studies, 1970 Rothbard, M., ?The Betrayal of the American Right?, Ludwig von Mises Institute, 2007 Taylor, Michael, ?Community, Anarchy and Liberty?, Cambridge University Press, 1985 Wolff, Jonathan, ?Robert Nozick. Property, Justice and the Minimal State?, Polity Press, 1991 Electronic journals: Casey, Gerard, (2013) ?Libertarian Anarchy: Against the State?, Notre Dame Philosophical Reviews. An Electronic Journal?, available at (http://ndpr.nd.edu/news/40697-libertarian-anarchy-against-the-state/), [accessed: 03/10/13]
SPREAD THE INFORMATION
Any information or special reports about various countries may be published with photos/videos on the world blog with bold legit source. All languages are welcome. Mail to lucschrijvers@hotmail.com.
Autobiography Luc Schrijvers Ebook €5 - Amazon
Search for an article in this Worldwide information blog
woensdag 11 juni 2014
(en) Britain, AFED Organise! #82 - To what extent are Nozick?s notions of self-ownership, inviolable liberty and capitalism valid?
Abonneren op:
Reacties posten (Atom)
Geen opmerkingen:
Een reactie posten